I was minding my own business on Twitter last week and noticed a slide posted with the image of the DSM-5. It did not take too long the realize that it was not posted by anyone who had read the DSM – at least not the first 25 pages. These pages are technically the introduction to the diagnostic section of the manual. Important words because they summarize the process, orient the reader to the manual, and describe several important qualifiers. That is how I was able to tell that the slide on Twitter had nothing to do with the DSM. The statements made about it were essentially false.
The first problem is the characterization that diagnoses
are “operational criteria” and that therefore it is a “fallible tool”. These
are common mistakes by anyone who has not been trained in medicine and the
understanding of disease states. For
simplicity, consider the definition from my physical diagnosis text from
medical school:
"For several thousand years physicians have
recorded observations and studies about their patients. In the
accumulating facts they have recognized patterns of disordered bodily
functions and structures as well as forms of mental aberration. When such
categories were sufficiently distinctive, they were termed diseases and
given specific names. “
DeGowan and DeGowan, Bedside
Diagnostic Examination. 1976, p 1
The introduction notes that the
precursor to the American Psychiatric Association (APA) published the
precursor to the DSM back in 1844. Even
before that, the description of psychiatric disorders stretches back for
thousands of years. The above definition notes the importance of patterns that
are consistent over time. A detailed
description of these patterns and those evolved descriptions is how all of
medicine has advanced. The other
important aspect of these descriptions is that they are sufficiently
descriptive. In the most basic
analysis, the DSM is the standard way that physicians have indexed diseases and
medical problems from the beginning. The
idea that it is merely “operational criteria” as in
arbitrary routine measurement is far from accurate. The introduction is very
clear that a diagnosis is not a checklist of symptoms and that a formulation is
required.
The fact that the DSM inconveniently contains a Neurocognitive Disorders chapter and qualifiers about ruling out all other medical illnesses as causes of the presenting disorder is typically not mentioned by the discrete pathological lesion crowd. If it is, the standard rhetoric that is applied goes something like this: "Well it is a disease it's just no longer a psychiatric disease. When real diseases are discovered they are no longer in the purview of psychiatry." Even though psychiatrists have been diagnosing and studying these diseases for over a hundred years.
There are often philosophical
digressions on the nature of mental illness and whether mental illness is a disease
or not. I have written fairly
extensively about that in other areas of this blog. For the purpose of addressing the slides I
will say that the lesion basis for both mental illnesses and physical illnesses
was addressed from within the field in response to the pathological theories by
Virchow and Koch. Interestingly, the answer to that theory was a study of
hypertension:
“It was in
fact the example of hypertension which finally discredited the
nineteenth-century assumption that there was always a qualitative distinction
between sickness and health. The demonstration by Pickering and his
colleagues twenty years ago (5) that such a major cause of death and disability
as this was a graded characteristic, dependent, like height and intelligence,
on polygenic inheritance and shading insensibly into normality, was greeted
with shock and disbelief by most of their contemporaries, and the prolonged
resistance to their findings showed how deeply rooted the assumptions of Koch
and Virchow had become.” (2)
Sixty years later, some academics
apparently still have a hard time realizing that mental illnesses are polygenic
illnesses of varying severity and a source of significant death and disability
and yet there is no clear qualitative difference between illness and disease
demarcated by a lesion. We are well past
the time that they should be ignored.
The current reality is this. The DSM consider mental disorders to be
disorders. They don’t address the issue of what is a disease and what is not.
The manual is very clear about their process and the fact that it is a work in
progress. That is nothing unique to psychiatry. Diagnoses are always in a state
of flux across all of medicine and that even includes diagnoses that are
defined by particular lesions. As the
science of medicine advances, expect more diagnoses and large diagnostic
categories like asthma, diabetes mellitus Type II, and depression to be broken
up into smaller and smaller categories that will probably correlate with
physiological findings. The authors of
DSM-5 are very clear that the manual is designed to be a cooperative document
with both NIMH Research Domain Criteria (RDoC) for research purposes and
International Classification of Diseases 11th revision (ICD-11) for
administrative an epidemiological purposes.
The good news is that if you are not a psychiatrist or mental health
clinician the details contained in the manual are probably not useful for you
to know. On my blog, I pointed out that
even primary care physicians don’t read it, so why would anyone else?
“If Szasz is right, the very idea that mental
illness is an illness depends on the idea that there is independent brain
pathology causing mental distress.”
She goes on to say that Szasz ”drew
a skeptical conclusion” from his own definition of brain disease and concluded
that most mental disorders were not brain diseases. I seem to be the only one
that recognizes that Szasz has been wrong about a lot of things for a long
time, most notably the restricted pathologically based view of any or all diseases.
That doesn’t seem to prevent it
from being dragged out time and time again. The realm of philosophers and
antipsychiatrists is apparently the only place Szasz is never wrong. And people
can say whatever they want about the DSM-5 – even if they clearly have not read
the first 25 pages.
George Dawson, MD, DFAPA
References:
1: Leonard A. The theories of Thomas Sydenham
(1624-1689). J R Coll Physicians Lond. 1990 Apr;24(2):141-3. PMID: 2191117;
PMCID: PMC5387565.
2: Kendell RE. The
concept of disease and its implications for psychiatry. Br J Psychiatry. 1975
Oct;127:305-15. doi: 10.1192/bjp.127.4.305. PMID: 1182384.
3: Smith R. In search of "non-disease". BMJ. 2002 Apr 13;324(7342):883-5. doi: 10.1136/bmj.324.7342.883. PMID: 11950739; PMCID: PMC1122831.
4: Meador CK. The
art and science of nondisease. N Engl J Med. 1965 Jan 14;272:92-5. doi:
10.1056/NEJM196501142720208. PMID: 14223129.
5: Oldham PD, Pickering
G, Fraser Roberts JA, Sowry GS. The nature of essential hypertension. Lancet.
1960 May 21;1(7134):1085-93. doi: 10.1016/s0140-6736(60)90982-x. PMID:
14428616.
6: Jefferson, A.
(2021). On Mental Illness and Broken Brains. Think, 20(58),
103-112. doi:10.1017/S1477175621000099
Graphics Credit:
Slides are all made by me with appropriate referencing. Click on any slide to enlarge.